Tuesday, August 10, 2010

Rule neutrality, rule naturality

Last week the website for the Workshop on Dialogues, Inference, and Proof - Logical and Empirical Perspectives (DIPLEAP) was distributed to the preliminary list of participants, which means Jesse and I need to start thinking about what we'll present there. One of us will certainly introduce N and cover the material in our ICLA paper, as sort of a test run. But since we've finished up the proof of the positive answer to the composition problem for N, I've been thinking about some more philosophical issues relating to the dialogical approach, and I might speak on these instead. Now that we have at least one example of a positive composition problem solution that was proved directly through semantic (that is, dialogical) means, the pot of gold at the end of the rainbow would be to be able to isolate what it was about the rules set N that allowed us to give this positive solution, so that we could then identify other rules sets where we can be sure a positive solution can be given, even if the proof strategy may differ. The composition problem proof for N relied crucially on our theorem characterizing the forms of valid implications in N, and this theorem in turn exploited the fact that when Felscher's rules E, D11, and D12 are dropped, Opponent can repeat defenses as many times as he want, and thus draw out a dialogue infinitely (meaning that Proponent cannot win). This fact is part of what made finding the proof for the composition problem so difficult: Neither of us have any clear intuition or understanding of what the connection is between Opponent's ability to repeat defenses and the theorems of N. There doesn't appear to be any fundamental fact grounding the connection, which means that it is extremely difficult to exploit, because working with N still feels like reaching out in the dark, blind. If we cannot pick out specifically something about the N rules that can be generalized or extrapolated to other rules sets, then perhaps it is still possible to say something general, to find a criterion/a for rule sets or a class of rule properties that have some connection, stronger or weaker, with a positive solution to the composition problem. That is, can we isolate some 'natural' feature of rules that is connected to the composition problem? One way to go about answering this is to look at rule sets where negative solutions to the composition problem can be given. We give an example in our paper on N, just to show that such examples can be given: Change the rules for CL so that Proponent is now allowed to also assert atoms in defense of disjunctions. Then, $\vDash p\vee\neg p$ and $\vDash(p\vee\neg p)\rightarrow p$, but $\nvDash p$, and thus the set of formulas generated by this rule set is not a logic. This example may seem somewhat trivial, but it actually displays an interesting property: The new rule fails to be neutral in the sense that it encodes an exception for a particular type of formula. This concept of neutrality seems like one that might be fruitfully exploited. First, we isolate three senses in which rules (both particle and structural) can be neutral:
  1. topic neutral (they do not favor one atom over another)
  2. connective neutral (they do not favor one connective over another)
  3. player neutral (they do not favor one player over another)
Then, we can ask: how much neutrality (a) is good and (b) can be had and obtain a logic? If neutrality turns out to be the right property to exploit, the latter question is the same as asking whether we can characterise when a rules set will have a positive solution to the composition problem on the basis of the neutrality of the rules involved. There are a few remarks that can be made at the outset. First, structural rules which are wholly player neutral will result in the inconsistent logic: Proponent has a winning strategy for every atom p, so at least some asymmetry/nonneutrality in the rules is required. This raises a question that I first became interested in in the cafe above the cafeteria on the campus in Ponta Delgada, which is how little player nonneutrality do we need in order to ensure that this does not follow? We already have reason to believe that D10 can be weakened, at least somewhat; Jesse has been investigating a variant of the D rules where Proponent can assert an atom if the corresponding literal has already been asserted by Opponent. The resulting rule set validates WEM but not LEM. (Thus, if this rule set generates a logic, then it is an SI-logic.) It is also likely that the particle rules cannot be wholly neutral: The fact that negations can only be attacked and not defended seems to be crucial. Investigating rule neutrality in these three ways has the advantage that neutrality is simply expressible, easy to determine, and has nice symmetry properties. However, the connection between neutrality of rules and their naturality is something which is much less clear, at this point. People working in the dialogical tradition who have tried to give philosophical justifications for the approach have appealed to the 'naturalness' of the rules (particularly the particle rules), and have argued that there is a connection between the dialogical rules and the way that people actually debate (see, for example, the first few pages of chapter 6 of Lorenzen's Constructive Philosophy), and that therefore the dialogical approach is philosophically preferable to others because it is somehow more natural. But what is 'natural'? Barthe & Krabbe, in From Axiom to Dialogue, after they have introduced rules for systematic dialectics and realistic dialectics (and before they discuss thoroughgoing dialectics, orderly dialectics, and dynamic dialectics), discuss the naturalness of the rules they've suggested:
In each case where we expect that the large majority of people can be brought to agree upon a certain rule as part of a formal_3 dialectics (provided they are explicitly confronted with it and made acquainted with the motivation given for it here or with a similar motivation), we shall say, for short, that we think it is a natural rule [p. 75].
If it is agreed that this is a reasonable definition of 'natural', then I think it can be argued that none of the dialogical rule sets are in fact natural. The motivation for many of the dialogical rule sets in the literature to date essentially boils down to "they work" -- a formal proof can be given showing that the rules do in fact correspond to the desired logic (or, in the case of N, that they correspond to a logic, even if that logic is one that was not set out in advance). The majority of people when confronted with this motivation are going to balk at being asked to accept the rules on that basis alone: They're going to ask, "Why do they work?" What is it about the rules that makes them correspond to a logic, much less the target logic isolated in advance? And now we're back to the original question: Are there any properties of rule or rule sets that correspond to positive solutions to the composition problem, and if so, what are they? And then neutrality of certain types presents itself again as a natural starting point for investigating answers.

3 comments:

  1. Another attempt to connect the particle rules to actual dialogical/debate experience is Witold Marciszewski, "Logic and Experience in the Light of Dialogical Logic", Bulletin of the Section of Logic Volume 12/4 (1983), pp. 173-178
    reedition 2008 [original edition, pp. 173-180].

    ReplyDelete
  2. From the implmentation of the code that evaluates dialogues rules, I can suggest another necessary condition for rule naturalness. Evaluating a rule on a sequence of dialogue moves amounts checking quantified statements like this:

    * for every move, ...

    * there is a move such that ...

    I would suggest that an *unnatural* rule would be one that cannot be understood as quantifying over the sequence of all previous moves. Such a rule would make a "bare" atomic statement, like:

    * The player of move 3 is Opponent.

    * The stance of move 2 is Defend.

    * Move 6 refers to move 1.

    One might also rule out conjunctions and disjunctions of atomic statements like this.

    One consideration against this notion of naturalness comes in when considering initial moves of the game:

    * The player of move 0 is Proponent.

    * The statement of move 0 is a non-atomic formula.

    These are actually expressed as rules in Felscher's paper; perhaps, though, they're not actually rules like the particle or structural rules.

    In any case, this is offered only as a necessary condition, not a sufficient one. One can imagine rules that, when expressed as logical statements about the sequence of proceeding moves, are quantified statements, but which are unnatural.

    ReplyDelete
  3. How about "move neutrality" as a name for this kind of condition? It makes sense to me, because we're using first-order quantification. I might add that the proposal could be sharpened a bit: the rules that interest us all have the form "for every move...". That is, they all begin with a universal quantification over the sequence of all previous moves.

    ReplyDelete